Qualities of a tragic protagonist in tragic poetry:
Aristotelian Model from Poetics
Aristotle
defined tragedy, as an imitation of action which is exalted and ‘serious’,
evoking the twin emotions of ‘pity and fear’ leading to ‘Catharsis’, a
purgation or cleansing of the emotions at the end. While defining tragedy
in his ‘Poetics’, Aristotle
realized that the tragic action requires a central agent to be carried out.
This agent or the conveyor of the tragic action is the tragic hero or tragic
protagonist.
An
Aristotelian tragic hero must possess specific characteristics, which can be
pointed out as having (i) Flaw or error of judgment- ‘hamartia’, (ii) A
reversal of fortune- ‘peripety’, brought about because of the hero's error in
judgment. (iii) The discovery or recognition that the reversal was brought
about by the hero's own actions- ‘anagnorisis’, (iv) Excessive Pride- ‘hubris’,
(v) The character's fate which leads him to the misfortunes- ‘nemesis’.
While
enumerating the characteristic features of the tragic hero, Aristotle first
takes up the perfectly good man and dismisses his journey from happiness to misery
as unfit for a tragic hero. The spectacle, he says of a blameless character
encountering suffering does not evoke pain in us, nor is it piteous; such a
sight of perfect innocence would evoke righteous anger instead of ‘pity and
fear’ and would therefore be not tragic in essence. Aristotle, then, considers
the viability of the completely bad man as a tragic hero. He says that such a
bad man passing from misery to happiness is also unsuitable for a tragic
situation. In fact, the spectacle of a bad man rising from misery to happiness
would be the most unfitting for tragedy, since it would be the grossest
violation of all our sense of poetic justice.Next comes the case of an
extremely bad man passing from happiness to misery. Even such a situation would
never arouse pity in us, nor would it evoke fear, since fear is the result of
our identification with the hero, and we can never completely identify our
selves with an agent of evil. Moreover, the sight of a guilty villain’s
suffering is basically pleasing to us and caters to our sense of poetic
justice.
There remains,
then, the intermediate kind of personage, “a man not pre-eminently virtuous and
just whose misfortune however is brought upon him not by vice and depravity,
but by some error of judgment. Aristotle exemplifies the characters of Oedipus
and Thyestes from the tragedies of Sophocles and Aeschylus respectively who
essentially fit the definition of a tragic hero. A tragic
hero therefore is socially exalted,elevated and grand whose downfall is not the
result of any moral lapse, but of some flaw or error of judgment that is ‘hamartia’
in Aristotle’s language.The phrase ‘error of judgment’ has
been a source of great confusion because the original Greek word ‘Hamartia’ is
actually a term taken from Archery, which means the missing of the mark by the
archer. Since the missing of the mark is not itself a culpable act, and often
proceeds from chance, many would argue that the hero is not himself guilty but
a victim of misfortune.
Aristotle’s
contentions about the tragic hero have been challenged by a host of modern critics
who contradict Aristotle on his observation that the perfectly good man is an
unfit character of tragedy. Pointing out stories from the Four
Gospels which present a history of suffering inflicted on perfect innocence. Christian
literature is filled with the stories of saints and martyrs who were destitute,
afflicted and tormented. Heroic greatness and perfect guiltlessness were the
secret of their power. In spite of the contentions, the vast majority of
tragedies seem to support Aristotle’s views. The very paucity of tragedy on the
blameless hero is itself the strongest argument in his favour. Moreover, those
characters embodying blameless goodness and perfect innocence seem to be so far
removed from the general sphere of fallible morality that such characters never
excite our sense of identification with them and, therefore, to arouse fear at
the spectacle of such tragic suffering is very difficult on the part of the
dramatist.
Thus it appears that over
and above all, Aristotle’s definition of the tragic hero is still
relevant. It is not worthy that Aristotle emphasizes the necessity of the
tragic hero being in the enjoyment of prosperity and regard. It is only on rare
occasions that the 20th century writers of tragedies such as Galsworthy with
his Strife or
Synge whit his Riders to the Sea,
has been able to make the ordinary character tragic. But this exception
only reinforces the general validity of the Aristotle principles of the tragic
protagonist.
No comments:
Post a Comment